The Report From Iron MountainA Satirical Indictment of RANDthink
Section 1: Scope of the Study
Section 2: Disarmament and the Economy
Section 3: Disarmament Scenarios
Section 4: War and Peace as Social Systems
Section 5: The Functions of War
Section 6: Substitutes for the Functions of War
Section 7: Summary and Conclusions
Section 8: Recommendations
We have completed our assignment to the best of our ability, subject to the limitations of time and resources available to us. Our conclusions of fact and our recommendations are unanimous; those of us who differ in certain secondary respects from the findings set forth herein do not consider these differences sufficient to warrant the filing of a minority report. It is our earnest hope that the fruits of our deliberations will be of value to our government in its efforts to provide leadership to the nation in solving the complex and far-reaching problems we have examined, and that our recommendations for subsequent Presidential action in this area will be adopted.
Because of the unusual circumstances surrounding the establishment of this Group, and in view of the nature of its finding, we do not recommend that this Report be released for publication. It is our affirmative judgement that such actions would not be in the public interest. The uncertain advantages of public discussion of our conclusions and recommendations are, in our opinion, greatly outweighed by the clear and predictable danger of a crisis in public confidence which untimely publication of this Report might be expected to provoke. The likelihood that a lay reader, unexposed to the exigencies of higher political or military responsibility, will misconstrue the purpose of this project, and the intent of its participants, seems obvious. We urge that circulation of this Report be closely restricted to those whose responsibilities require that they be apprised of its contents.
We deeply regret that the necessity of anonymity, a prerequisite to
our Group's unhindered pursuit of its objectives, precludes proper acknowledgement
of our gratitude to the many persons in and out of government who contributed
so greatly to our work.
For the Special Study Group
[signature withheld]
30 September, 1966
Our work has been predicated on the belief that some kind of general peace may soon be negotiable. The de facto admission of Communist China into the United Nations now appears to be only a few years away at most. It has become increasingly manifest that conflicts of American national interest with those of China and the Soviet Union are susceptible of political solution, despite the superficial contraindications of the current Vietnam war, of the threats of an attack on China, and of the necessarily hostile tenor of day-to-day foreign policy statements. It is also obvious that differences involving other nations can be readily resolved by the three great powers whenever they arrive at a stable peace among themselves. It is not necessary, for the purposes of our study, to assume that a general detente of this sort will come about - and we make no such argument - but only that it may.
It is surely no exaggeration to say that a condition of general world peace would lead to changes in the social structures of the nations of the world of unparalleled and revolutionary magnitude. The economic impact of general disarmament, to name only the most obvious consequence of peace, would revise the production and distribution patterns of the globe to a degree that would make the changes of the past fifty years seem insignificant. Political, sociological, cultural, and ecological changes would be equally far-reaching. What has motivated our study of these contingencies has been the growing sense of thoughtful men in and out of government that the world is totally unprepared to meet the demands of such a situation.
We had originally planned, when our study was initiated, to address ourselves to these two broad questions and their components: What can be expected if peace comes? What should we be prepared to do about it? But as our investigation proceeded it became apparent that certain other questions had to be faced. What, for instance, are the real functions of war in modern societies, beyond the ostensible ones of defending and advancing the "national interests" of nations? In the absence of war, what other institutions exist or might be devised to fulfill these functions? Granting that a "peaceful" settlement of disputes is within the range of current international relationships, is the abolition of war, in the broad sense, really possible? If so, is it necessarily desirable, in terms of social stability? If not, what can be done to improve the operation of our social system in respect to its war-readiness?
The word peace, as we have used it in the following pages, describes a permanent, or quasi-permanent, condition entirely free from the national exercise, or contemplation, of any form of the organized social violence, or threat of violence, generally known as war. It implies total and general disarmament. It is not used to describe the more familiar condition of "cold war," "armed peace, " or other mere respite, long or short, from armed conflict. Nor is it used simply as a synonym for the political settlement of international differences. The magnitude of modern means of mass destruction and the speed of modern communications require the unqualified working definition given above; only a generation ago such an absolute description would have seemed utopian rather than pragmatic. Today, any modification of this definition would render it almost worthless for our purpose. By the same standard, we have used the word war to apply interchangeably to conventional ("hot") war, to the general condition of war preparation or war readiness, and to the general "war system." The sense intended is made clear in context.
The first section of our Report deals with its scope and with the assumptions on which our study was based. The second considers the effects of disarmament on the economy, the subject of most peace research to date. The third takes up so-called "disarmament scenarios" which have been proposed. The fourth, fifth, and sixth examine the nonmilitary functions of war and the problems they raise for a viable transition to peace; here will be found some indications of the true dimensions of the problem, not previously coordinated in any other study. In the seventh section we summarize our findings, and in the eighth we set forth our recommendations for what we believe to be a practical and necessary course of action.
1) military-style objectivity;
2) avoidance of preconceived value assumptions;
3) inclusion of all relevant areas of theory and data.
It is a truism that objectivity is more often an intention expressed than an attitude achieved, but the intention - conscious, unambiguous, and constantly self-critical - is a precondition to its achievement. We believe it no accident that we were charged to use a "military contingency" model for our study, and we owe a considerable debt to the civilian war planning agencies for their pioneering work in the objective examination of the contingencies of nuclear war. There is no such precedent in peace studies. Much of the usefulness of even the most elaborate and carefully reasoned programs for economic conversion to peace, for example, has been vitiated by a wishful eagerness to demonstrate that peace is not only possible, but even cheap or easy. One official report is replete with references to the critical role of "dynamic optimism" on economic developments, and goes on to submit, as evidence, that it "would be hard to imagine that the American people would not respond very positively to an agreed and safeguarded program to substitute an international rule of law and order," etc. [1] Another line of argument frequently taken is that disarmament would entail comparatively little disruption of the economy, since it need only be partial; we will deal with this approach later. Yet genuine objectivity in war studies is often criticized as inhuman. As Herman Kahn, the writer on strategic studies best known to the general public, put it: "Critics frequently object to the icy rationality of the Hudson Institute, the Rand Corporation, and other such organizations. I'm always tempted to ask in reply, 'Would you prefer a warm, human error? Do you feel better with a nice emotional mistake?'" [2] And, as Secretary of Defense Robert S. McNamara has pointed out, in reference to facing up to the possibility of nuclear war, "Some people are afraid even to look over the edge. But in a thermonuclear war we cannot afford any political acrophobia." [3] Surely it should be self-evident that this applies equally to the opposite prospect, but so far no one has taken more than a timid glance over the brink of peace.
An intention to avoid preconceived value judgments is if anything even
more productive of self-delusion. We claim no immunity, as individuals,
from this type of bias, but we have made a continuously self-conscious
effort to deal with the problems of peace without, for example, considering
that a condition of peace is per se "good" or "bad." This
has not been easy, but it has been obligatory; to our knowledge, it has
not been done before. Previous studies have taken the desirability of peace,
the importance of human life, the superiority of democratic institutions,
the greatest "good" for the greatest number, the "dignity" of the individual,
the desirability of maximum health and longevity, and other such wishful
premises as axiomatic values necessary for the justification of a study
of peace issues. We have not found them so. We have attempted to apply
the standards of physical science to our thinking, the principal characteristic
of which is not quantification, as is popularly believed, but that, in
Whitehead's words, "... it ignores all judgments of value; for instance,
all esthetic and moral judgments." [4] Yet it is obvious
that any serious investigation of a problem, however "pure," must be informed
by some normative standard. In this case it has been simply the survival
of human society in general, of American society in particular, and, as
a corollary to survival, the stability of this society.
It is interesting, we believe, to note that the most dispassionate
planners of nuclear strategy also recognize that the stability of society
is the one bedrock value that cannot be avoided. Secretary
McNamara has defended the need for American nuclear superiority on the
grounds that it "makes possible a strategy designed to preserve the fabric
of our societies if war should occur." [5] A former member
of the Department of State policy planning staff goes further. "A more
precise word for peace, in terms of the practical world, is stability.
... Today the great nuclear panoplies are essential elements in such stability
as exists. Our present purpose must be to continue the process of learning
how to live with them." [6] We, of course, do not equate
stability with peace, but we accept it as the one common assumed objective
of both peace and war.
The third criterion - breadth - has taken us still farther afield from peace studies made to date. It is obvious to any layman that the economic patterns of a warless world will be drastically different from those we live with today, and it is equally obvious that the political relationships of nations will not be those we have learned to take for granted, sometimes described as a global version of the adversary system of our common law. But the social implications of peace extend far beyond its putative effects on national economies and international relations. As we shall show, the relevance of peace and war to the internal political organization of societies, to the sociological relationships of their members, to psychological motivations, to ecological processes, and to cultural values is equally profound. More important, it is equally critical in assaying the consequences of a transition to peace, and in determining the feasibility of any transition at all.
It is not surprising that these less obvious factors have been generally ignored in peace research. They have not lent themselves to systematic analysis. They have been difficult, perhaps impossible, to measure with any degree of assurance that estimates of their effects could be depended on. They are "intangibles," but only in the sense that abstract concepts in mathematics are intangible compared to those which can be measured, at least superficially; and international relationships can be verbalized, like law, into logical sequences.
We do not claim that we have discovered an infallible way of measuring these other factors, or of assigning them precise weights in the equation of transition. But we believe we have taken their relative importance into account to this extent: we have removed them from the category of the "intangible," hence scientifically suspect and therefore somehow of secondary importance, and brought them out into the realm of the objective. The result, we believe, provides a context of realism for the discussion of the issues relating to the possible transition to peace which up to now has been missing.
This is not to say that we presume to have found the answers we were seeking. But we believe that our emphasis on breadth of scope has made it at least possible to begin to understand the questions.
General agreement prevails with respect to the more important economic problems that general disarmament would raise. A short survey of these problems, rather than a detailed critique of their comparative significance, is sufficient for our purposes in this Report.
The first factor is that of size. The "world war industry," as one writer [7] has aptly called it, accounts for approximately a tenth of the output of the world's total economy. Although this figure is subject to fluctuation, the causes of which are themselves subject to regional variation, it tends to hold fairly steady. The United States, as the world's richest nation, not only accounts for the largest single share of this expense, currently upward of $60 billion a year, but also "... has devoted a higher proportion [emphasis added] of its gross national product to its military establishment than any other major free world nation. This was true even before our increased expenditures in Southeast Asia." [8] Plans for economic conversion that minimize the economic magnitude of the problem do so only by rationalizing, however persuasively, the maintenance of a substantial residual military budget under some euphemized classification.
Conversion of military expenditures to other purposes entails a number of difficulties. The most serious stems from the degree of high specialization that characterizes modern war production, best exemplified in nuclear and missile technology. This constituted no fundamental problem after World War II, nor did the question of free-market consumer demand for "conventional" items of consumption - those goods and service consumers had already been conditioned to require. Today's situation is qualitatively different in both respects.
This inflexibility is geographical and occupational, as well as industrial, a fact which has led most analysts of the economic impact of disarmament to focus their attention on phased plans for the relocation of war industry personnel and capital installations as much as on proposals for developing new patterns of consumption. One serious flaw common to such plans is the kind called in the natural sciences the "macroscopic error." An implicit presumption is made that a total national plan for conversion differs from a community program to cope with the shutting down of a "defense facility" only in degree. We find no reason to believe that this is the case, nor that a general enlargement of such local programs, however well thought out in terms of housing, occupational retraining, and the like, can be applied on a national scale. A national economy can absorb almost any number of subsidiary reorganizations within its total limits, providing there is no basic change in its own structure. General disarmament, which would require such basic changes, lends itself to no valid smaller-scale analogy.
Even more questionable are the models proposed for the retraining of labor for nonarmaments occupation. Putting aside for the moment the unsolved questions dealing with the nature of new distribution patterns - retraining for what? - the increasingly specialized job skills associated with war industry production are further depreciated by the accelerating inroads of the industrial techniques loosely described as "automation." It is not too much to say that general disarmament would require the scrapping of a critical proportion of the most highly developed occupational specialties in the economy. The political difficulties inherent in such an "adjustment" would make the outcries resulting from the closing of a few obsolete military and naval installations in 1964 sound like a whisper.
In general, discussion of the problems of conversion have been characterized by an unwillingness to recognize its special quality. This is best exemplified by the 1965 report of the Ackley Committee. [9] One critic has tellingly pointed out that it blindly assumes that "... nothing in the arms economy - neither its size, nor its geographical concentration, nor its highly specialized nature, nor the peculiarities of its market, nor the special nature of much of its labor force - endows it with any uniqueness when the necessary time of adjustment comes." [10]
Let us assume, however, despite the lack of evidence that a viable program for conversion can be developed in the framework of the existing economy, that the problems noted above can be solved. What proposals have been offered for utilizing the productive capabilities that disarmament would presumably release?
The most commonly held theory is simply that general economic reinvestment would absorb the greater part of these capabilities. Even though it is now largely taken for granted (and even by today's equivalent of traditional laissez-faire economists) that unprecedented government assistance (and concomitant government control) will be needed to solve the "structural" problems of transition, a general attitude of confidence prevails that new consumption patterns will take up the slack. What is less clear is the nature of these patterns.
One school of economists has it that these patterns will develop on their own. It envisages the equivalent of the arms budget being returned, under careful control, to the consumer, in the form of tax cuts. Another, recognizing the undeniable need for increased "consumption" in what is generally considered the public sector of the economy, stresses vastly increased government spending in such areas of national concern as health, education, mass transportation, low-cost housing, water supply, control of the physical environment, and, stated generally, "poverty."
The mechanisms proposed for controlling the transition to an arms-free economy are also traditional - changes in both sides of the federal budget, manipulation of interest rates, etc. We acknowledge the undeniable value of fiscal tools in a normal cyclical economy, where they provide leverage to accelerate or brake an existing trend. Their more committed proponents, however, tend to lose sight of the fact that there is a limit to the power of these devices to influence fundamental economic forces. They can provide new incentives in the economy, but they cannot in themselves transform the production of a billion dollars' worth of missiles a year to the equivalent in food, clothing, prefabricated houses, or television sets. At bottom, they reflect the economy; they do not motivate it.
More sophisticated, and less sanguine analysts contemplate the diversion of the arms budget to a nonmilitary system equally remote from the market economy. What the "pyramid-builders" frequently suggest is the expansion of space-research programs to the dollar level of current armaments expenditures. This approach has the superficial merit of reducing the size of the problem of transferability of resources, but introduces other difficulties, which we will take up in section 6.
Without singling out any one of the several major studies of the expected impact of disarmament on the economy for special criticism, we can summarize our objections to them in general terms as follows:
All such scenarios that have been seriously put forth imply dependence on bilateral or multilateral agreement between the great powers. In general, they call for a progressive phasing out of gross armaments, military forces, weapons, and weapons technology, coordinated with elaborate matching procedures of verification, inspection, and machinery for the settlement of international disputes. It should be noted that even proponents of unilateral disarmament qualify their proposals with an implied requirement of reciprocity, very much in the manner of a scenario of graduated response in nuclear war. The advantage of unilateral initiative lies in its political value as an expression of good faith, as well as in its diplomatic function as a catalyst for formal disarmament negotiations.
The READ model for disarmament (developed by the Research Program on Economic Adjustments to Disarmament) is typical of these scenarios. It is a twelve-year-program, divided into three-year stages. Each stage includes a separate phase of: reduction of armed forces; cutbacks of weapons production, inventories, and foreign military bases; development of international inspection procedures and control conventions; and the building up of a sovereign international disarmament organization. It anticipates a net matching decline in U.S. defense expenditures of only somewhat more than half the 1965 level, but a necessary redeployment of some five-sixths of the defense-dependent labor force.
The economic implications assigned by their authors to various disarmament scenarios diverge widely. The more conservative models, like that cited above, emphasize economic as well as military prudence in postulating elaborate fail-safe disarmament agencies, which themselves require expenditures substantially substituting for those of the displaced war industries. Such programs stress the advantages of the smaller economic adjustment entailed. [11] Others emphasize, on the contrary, the magnitude (and the opposite advantages) of the savings to be achieved from disarmament. One widely read analysis [12] estimates the annual cost of the inspection function of general disarmament throughout the world as only between two and three percent of current military expenditures. Both types of plan tend to deal with the anticipated problem of economic reinvestment only in the aggregate. We have seen no proposed disarmament sequence that correlates the phasing out of specific kinds of military spending with specific new forms of substitute spending.
Without examining disarmament scenarios in greater detail, we may characterize them with these general comments:
Some essential element has clearly been lacking in all these schemes. One of our first tasks was to try to bring this missing quality into definable focus, and we believe we have succeeded in doing so. We find that at the heart of every peace study we have examined - from the modest technological proposal (e.g., to convert a poison gas plant to the production of "socially useful" equivalents) to the most elaborate scenario for universal peace in our time - lies one common fundamental misconception. It is the source of the miasma of unreality surrounding such plans. It is the incorrect assumption that war, as an institution, is subordinate to the social systems it is believed to serve.
This misconception, although profound and far-reaching, is entirely comprehensible. Few social cliches are so unquestioningly accepted as the notion that war is an extension of diplomacy (or of politics, or of the pursuit of economic objectives). If this were true, it would be wholly appropriate for economists and political theorists to look on the problems of transition to peace as essentially mechanical or procedural - as indeed they do, treating them as logistic corollaries of the settlement of national conflicts of interest. If this were true, there would be no real substance to the difficulties of transition. For it is evident that even in today's world there exists no conceivable conflict of interest, real or imaginary, between nations or between social forces within nation, that cannot be resolved without recourse to war - if such resolution were assigned a priority of social value. And if this were true, the economic analyses and disarmament proposals we have referred to, plausible and well conceived as they may be, would not inspire, as they do, an inescapable sense of indirection.
The point is that the cliche is not true, and the problems of transition are indeed substantive rather than merely procedural. Although war is "used" as an instrument of national and social policy, the fact that a society is organized for any degree of readiness for war supersedes its political and economic structure. War itself is the basic social system, within which other secondary modes of social organization conflict or conspire. It is the system which has governed most human societies of record, as it is today.
Once this is correctly understood, the true magnitude of the problems entailed in a transition to peace - itself a social system, but without precedent except in a few simple preindustrial societies - becomes apparent. At the same time, some of the puzzling superficial contradictions of modern societies can then be readily rationalized. The "unnecessary" size and power of the world war industry; the preeminence of the military establishment in every society, whether open or concealed; the exemption of military or paramilitary institutions from the accepted social and legal standards for behavior required elsewhere in the society; the successful operation of the armed forces and the armaments producers entirely outside the framework of each nation's economic ground rules: these and other ambiguities closely associated with the relationship of war to society are easily clarified, once the priority of war-making potential as the principal structuring force in society is accepted. Economic systems, political philosophies, and corpora jures serve and extend the war system, not vice versa.
It must be emphasized that the precedence of a society's war-making potential over its other characteristics is not the result of the "threat" presumed to exist at any one time from other societies. This is the reverse of the basic situation; "threats" against the "national interest" are usually created or accelerated to meet the changing needs of the war system. Only in comparatively recent times has it been considered politically expedient to euphemize war budgets as "defense" requirements. The necessity for governments to distinguish between "aggression" (bad) and "defense" (good) has been a by-product of rising literacy and rapid communication. The distinction is tactical only, a concession to the growing inadequacy of ancient war-organizing political rationales.
Wars are not "caused" by international conflicts of interest. Proper logical sequence would make it more often accurate to say that war-making societies require - and thus bring about - such conflicts. The capacity of a nation to make war expresses the greatest social power it can exercise; war-making, active or contemplated, is a matter of life and death on the greatest scale subject to social control. It should therefore hardly be surprising that the military institutions in each society claim its highest priorities.
We find further that most of the confusion surrounding the myth that war-making is a tool of state policy stems from a general misapprehension of the functions of war. In general, these are conceived as: to defend a nation from military attack by another, or to deter such an attack; to defend or advance a "national interest" - economic, political, ideological; to maintain or increase a nation's military power for its own sake. These are the visible, or ostensible, functions of war. If there were no others, the importance of the war establishment in each society might in fact decline to the subordinate level it is believed to occupy. And the elimination of war would indeed be the procedural matter that the disarmament scenarios suggest.
But there are other, broader, more profoundly felt functions of war in modern societies. It is these invisible, or implied, functions that maintain war-readiness as the dominant force in our societies. And it is the unwillingness or inability of the writers of disarmament scenarios and reconversion plans to take them into account that has so reduced the usefulness of their work, and that has made it seem unrelated to the world we know.
We propose in this section to examine these nonmilitary, implied, and usually invisible functions of war, to the extent they they bear on the problems of transition to peace for our society. The military, or ostensible, function of the war system requires no elaboration; it serves simply to defend or advance the "national interest" by means of organized violence. It is often necessary for a national military establishment to create a need for its unique powers - to maintain the franchise, so to speak. And a healthy military apparatus requires regular "exercise," by whatever rationale seems expedient, to prevent its atrophy.
The nonmilitary functions of the war system are more basic. They exist not merely to justify themselves but to serve broader social purposes. If and when war is eliminated, the military functions it has served will end with it. But its nonmilitary functions will not. It is essential, therefore, that we understand their significance before we can reasonably expect to evaluate whatever institutions may be proposed to replace them.
The production of weapons of mass destruction has always been associated with economic "waste." The term is pejorative, since it implies a failure of function. But no human activity can properly be considered wasteful if it achieves its contextual objective. The phrase "wasteful but necessary," applied not only to war expenditures, but to most of the "unproductive" commercial activities of our society, is a contradiction in terms. "... The attacks that have since the time of Samuel's criticism of King Saul been leveled against military expenditures as waste may well have concealed or misunderstood the point that some kinds of waste may have a larger social utility." [13]
In the case of military "waste," there is indeed a larger social utility. It derives from the fact that the "wastefulness" of war production is exercised entirely outside the framework of the economy of supply and demand. As such, it provides the only critically large segment of the total economy that is subject to complete and arbitrary central control. If modern industrial societies can be defined as those which have developed the capacity to produce more than is required for their economic survival (regardless of the equities of distribution of goods within them), military spending can be said to furnish the only balance wheel with sufficient inertia to stabilize the advance of their economies. The fact that war is "wasteful" is what enables it to serve this function. And the faster the economy advances, the heavier this balance wheel must be.
This function is often viewed, oversimply, as a device for the control of surpluses. One writer on the subject puts it this way: "Why is war so wonderful? Because it creates artificial demand ... the only kind of artificial demand, moreover, that does not raise any political issues: war, and only war, solves the problem of inventory." [14] The reference here is to shooting war, but it applies equally to the general war economy as well. "It is generally agreed," concludes, more cautiously, the report of a panel set up by the U.S. Arms Control and Disarmament Agency, "that the greatly expanded public sector since World War II, resulting from heavy defense expenditures, has provided additional protection against depressions, since this sector is not responsive to contraction in the private sector and has provided a sort of buffer or balance wheel in the economy." [15]
The principal economic function of war, in our view, is that it provides just such a flywheel. It is not to be confused in function with the the various forms of fiscal control, none of which directly engages vast numbers of men and units of production. It is not to be confused with massive government expenditures in social welfare programs; once initiated, such programs normally become integral parts of the general economy and are no longer subject to arbitrary control.
But even in the context of the general civilian economy war cannot be considered wholly "wasteful." Without a long-established war economy, and without its frequent eruption into large-scale shooting war, most of the major industrial advances known to history, beginning with the development of iron, could never have taken place. Weapons technology structures the economy. According to the writer cited above, "Nothing is more ironic or revealing about our society than the fact that hugely destructive war is a very progressive force in it. ... War production is progressive because it is production that would not otherwise have taken place. (It is not so widely appreciated, for example, that the civilian standard of living rose during World War II.)" [16] This is not "ironic or revealing," but essentially a simple statement of fact.
It should also be noted that war production has a dependable stimulation effect outside itself. Far from constituting a "wasteful" drain on the economy, war spending, considered pragmatically, has been a consistently positive factor in the rise of gross national product and of individual productivity. A former Secretary of the Army has carefully phrased it for public consumption thus: "If there is, as I suspect there is, a direct relation between the stimulus of large defense spending and a substantially increased rate of growth of gross national product, it quite simply follows that defense spending per se might be countenanced on economic grounds alone [emphasis added] as a stimulator of the national metabolism." [17] Actually, the fundamental nonmilitary utility of war in the economy is far more widely acknowledged than the scarcity of such affirmations as that quoted above would suggest.
But negatively phrased public recognitions of the importance of war to the general economy abound. The most familiar example is the effect of the "peace threats" on the stock market, e.g., "Wall Street was shaken yesterday by news of an apparent peace feeler from North Vietnam, but swiftly recovered its composure after about an hour of sometimes indiscriminate selling." [18] Savings banks solicit deposits with similar cautionary slogans, e.g., "If peace breaks out, will you be ready for it?" A more subtle case in point was the recent refusal of the Department of Defense to permit the West German government to substitute nonmilitary goods for unwanted armaments in its purchase commitments from the United States; the decisive consideration was that the German purchases should not affect the general (nonmilitary) economy. Other incidental examples are to be found in the pressures brought to bear on the Department when it announces plans to close down an obsolete facility (as a "wasteful" form of "waste"), and in the usual coordination of stepped-up military activities (as in Vietnam in 1965) with dangerously rising unemployment rates.
Although we do not imply that a substitute for war in the economy cannot be devised, no combination of techniques for controlling employment, production, and consumption has yet been tested that can remotely compare to it in effectiveness. It is, and has been, the essential economic stabilizer of modern societies.
The political functions of war have been up to now even more critical to social stability. It is not surprising, nevertheless, that discussions of economic conversion for peace tend to fall silent on the matter of political implementation, and that disarmament scenarios, often sophisticated in their weighing of international political factors, tend to disregard the political functions of the war system within individual societies.
These functions are essentially organizational. First of all, the existence of a society as a political "nation" requires as part of its definition an attitude of relationship toward other "nations." This is what we usually call a foreign policy. But a nation's foreign policy can have no substance if it lacks the means of enforcing its attitude toward other nations. It can do this in a credible manner only if it implies the threat of maximum political organization for this purpose - which is to say that it is organized to some degree for war. War, then, as we have defined it to include all national activities that recognize the possibility of armed conflict, is itself the defining element of any nation's existence vis-a-vis any other nation. Since it is historically axiomatic that the existence of any form of weaponry insures its use, we have used the word "peace" as virtually synonymous with disarmament. By the same token, "war" is virtually synonymous with nationhood. The elimination of war implies the inevitable elimination of national sovereignty and the traditional nation-state.
The war system not only has been essential to the existence of nations as independent political entities, but has been equally indispensable to their stable internal political structure. Without it, no government has ever been able to obtain acquiescence in its "legitimacy," or right to rule its society. The possibility of war provides the sense of external necessity without which no government can long remain in power. The historical record reveals one instance after another where the failure of a regime to maintain the credibility of a war threat led to its dissolution, by the forces of private interest, of reactions to social injustice, or of other disintegrative elements. The organization of a society for the possibility of war is its principal political stabilizer. It is ironic that this primary function of war has been generally recognized by historians only where it has been expressly acknowledged - in the pirate societies of the great conquerors.
The basic authority of a modern state over its people resides in its war powers. (There is, in fact, good reason to believe that codified law had its origins in the rules of conduct established by military victors for dealing with the defeated enemy, which were later adapted to apply to all subject populations. [19]) On a day-to-day basis, it is represented by the institution of police, armed organizations charged expressly with dealing with "internal enemies" in a military manner. Like the conventional "external" military, the police are also substantially exempt from many civilian legal restraints on their social behavior. In some countries, the artificial distinction between police and other military forces does not exist. On the long-term basis, a government's emergency war powers - inherent in the structure of even the most libertarian of nations - define the most significant aspect of the relation between state and citizen.
In advanced modern democratic societies, the war system has provided political leaders with another political-economic function of increasing importance: it has served as the last great safeguard against the elimination of necessary social classes. As economic productivity increases to a level further and further above that of minimum subsistence, it becomes more and more difficult for a society to maintain distribution patterns insuring the existence of "hewers of wood and drawers of water." The further progress of automation can be expected to differentiate still more sharply between "superior" workers and what Ricardo called "menials," while simultaneously aggravating the problem of maintaining an unskilled labor supply.
The arbitrary nature of war expenditures and of other military activities make them ideally suited to control these essential class relationships. Obviously, if the war system were to be discarded, new political machinery would be needed at once to serve this vital subfunction. Until it is developed, the continuance of the war system must be assured, if for no other reason, among others, than to preserve whatever quality and degree of poverty a society requires as an incentive, as well as to maintain the stability of its internal organization of power.
Under this heading, we will examine a nexus of functions served by the war system that affect human behavior in society. In general, they are broader in application and less susceptible to direct observation than the economic and political factors previously considered.
The most obvious of these functions is the time-honored use of military institutions to provide antisocial elements with an acceptable role in the social structure. The disintegrative, unstable social movements loosely described as "fascist" have traditionally taken root in societies that have lacked adequate military or paramilitary outlets to meet the needs of these elements. This function has been critical in periods of rapid change. The danger signals are easy to recognize, even though the stigmata bear different names at different times. The current euphemistic cliches - "juvenile delinquency" and "alienation" - have had their counterparts in every age. In earlier days these conditions were dealt with directly by the military without the complications of due process, usually through press gangs or outright enslavement. But it is not hard to visualize, for example, the degree of social disruption that might have taken place in the United States during the last two decades if the problem of the socially disaffected of the post-World War II period had not been foreseen and effectively met. The younger, and more dangerous, of these hostile social groupings have been kept under control by the Selective Service System.
This system and its analogues elsewhere furnish remarkably clear examples of disguised military utility. Informed persons in this country have never accepted the official rationale for a peacetime draft - military necessity, preparedness, etc. - as worthy of serious consideration. But what has gained credence among thoughtful men is the rarely voiced, less easily refuted, proposition that the institution of military service has a "patriotic" priority in our society that must be maintained for its own sake. Ironically, the simplistic official justification for selective service comes closer to the mark, once the nonmilitary functions of military institutions are understood. As a control device over the hostile, nihilistic, and potentially unsettling elements of a society in transition, the draft can again be defended, and quite convincingly, as a "military" necessity.
Nor can it be considered a coincidence that overt military activity, and thus the level of draft calls, tend to follow the major fluctuations in the unemployment rate in the lower age groups. This rate, in turn, is a time-tested herald of social discontent. It must be noted also that the armed forces in every civilization have provided the principal state-supported haven for what are now called the "unemployable." The typical European standing army (of fifty years ago) consisted of "... troops unfit for employment in commerce, industry, or agriculture, led by officers unfit to practice any legitimate profession or to conduct a business enterprise." [20] This is still largely true, if less apparent. In a sense, this function of the military as the custodian of the economically or culturally deprived was the forerunner of most contemporary civilian social-welfare programs, from the W.P.A. to various forms of "socialized" medicine and social security. It is interesting that liberal sociologists currently proposing to use the Selective Service System as a medium of cultural upgrading of the poor consider this a novel application of military practice.
Although it cannot be said absolutely that such critical measures of social control as the draft require a military rationale, no modern society has yet been willing to risk experimentation with any other kind. Even during such periods of comparatively simple social crisis as the so-called Great Depression of the 1930s, it was deemed prudent by the government to invest minor make-work projects, like "Civilian" Conservation Corps, with a military character, and to place the more ambitious National Recovery Administration under the direction of a professional army officer at its inception. Today, at least one small Northern European country, plagued with uncontrollable unrest among its "alienated youth," is considering the expansion of its armed forces, despite the problem of making credible the expansion of a non-existent external threat.
Sporadic efforts have been made to promote general recognition of broad national values free of military connotation, but they have been ineffective. For example, to enlist public support of even such modest programs of social adjustment as "fighting inflation" or "maintaining physical fitness" it has been necessary for the government to utilize a patriotic (i.e., military) incentive. It sells "defense" bonds and it equates health with military preparedness. This is not surprising; since the concept of "nationhood" implies readiness for war, a "national" program must do likewise.
In general, the war system provides the basic motivation for primary social organization. In so doing, it reflects on the societal level the incentives of individual human behavior. The most important of these, for social purposes, is the individual psychological rationale for allegiance to a society and its values. Allegiance requires a cause; a cause requires an enemy. This much is obvious; the critical point is that the enemy that defines the cause must seem genuinely formidable. Roughly speaking, the presumed power of the "enemy" sufficient to warrant an individual sense of allegiance to a society must be proportionate to the size and complexity of the society. Today, of course, that power must be one of unprecedented magnitude and frightfulness.
It follows, from the patterns of human behavior, that the credibility of a social "enemy" demands similarly a readiness of response in proportion to its menace. In a broad social context, "an eye for an eye" still characterizes the only acceptable attitude toward a presumed threat of aggression, despite contrary religious and moral precepts governing personal conduct. The remoteness of personal decision from social consequence in a modern society makes it easy for its members to maintain this attitude without being aware of it. A recent example is the war in Vietnam; a less recent one was the bombing of Hiroshima and Nagasaki. [21] In each case, the extent and gratuitousness of the slaughter were abstracted into political formulae by most Americans, once the proposition that the victims were "enemies" was established. The war system makes such an abstracted response possible in nonmilitary contexts as well. A conventional example of this mechanism is the inability of most people to connect, let us say, the starvation of millions in India with their own past conscious political decision-making. Yet the sequential logic linking a decision to restrict grain production in America with an eventual famine in Asia is obvious, unambiguous, and unconcealed.
What gives the war system its preeminent role in social organization, as elsewhere, is its unmatched authority over life and death. It must be emphasized again that the war system is not a mere social extension of the presumed need for individual human violence, but itself in turn serves to rationalize most nonmilitary killing. It also provides the precedent for collective willingness of members of a society to pay a blood price for institutions far less central to social organization than war. To take a handy example, "... rather than accept speed limits of twenty miles an hour we prefer to let automobiles kill forty thousand people a year." [22] A Rand analyst puts it in more general terms and less rhetorically: "I am sure that there is, in effect, a desirable level of automobile accidents - desirable, that is, from a broad point of view; in the sense that it is a necessary concomitant of things of greater value to society." [23] The point may seem too obvious for iteration, but is essential to an understanding of the important motivational function of war as a model for collective sacrifice.
A brief look at some defunct premodern societies is instructive. One of the most noteworthy features common to the larger, more complex, and more successful of ancient civilizations was their widespread use of the blood sacrifice. If one were to limit consideration to those cultures whose regional hegemony was so complete that the prospect of "war" had become virtually inconceivable - as was the case with several of the great pre-Columbian societies of the Western Hemisphere - it would be found that some form of ritual killing occupied a position of paramount social importance in each. Invariably, the ritual was invested with mythic or religious significance; as with all religious and totemic practice, however, the ritual masked a broader and more important social function.
In these societies, the blood sacrifice served the purpose of maintaining a vestigial "earnest" of the society's capability and willingness to make war - i.e., kill and be killed - in the event that some mystical - i.e., unforeseen - circumstance were to give rise to the possibility. That the "earnest" was not an adequate substitute for genuine military organization when the unthinkable enemy, such as the Spanish conquistadores, actually appeared on the scene in no way negates the function of the ritual. It was primarily, if not exclusively, a symbolic reminder that war had once been the central organizing force of the society, and that this condition might recur.
It does not follow that a transition to total peace in modern societies would require the use of this model, even in less "barbaric" guise. But the historical analogy serves as a reminder that a viable substitute for war as a social system cannot be a mere symbolic charade. It must involve real risk of real personal destruction, and on a scale consistent with the size and complexity of modern social systems. Credibility is the key. Whether the substitute is ritual in nature or functionally substantive, unless it provides a believable life-and-death threat it will not serve the socially organizing function of war.
The existence of an accepted external menace, then, is essential to social cohesiveness as well as to the acceptance of political authority. The menace must be believable, it must be of a magnitude consistent with the complexity of the society threatened, and it must appear, at least, to affect the entire society.
Man, like all other animals, is subject to the continuing process of adapting to the limitations of his environment. But the principal mechanism he has utilized for this purpose is unique among living creatures. To forestall the inevitable historical cycles of inadequate food supply, post-Neolithic man destroys surplus members of his own species by organized warfare.
Ethologists [24] have often observed that the organized slaughter of members of their own species is virtually unknown among other animals. Man's special propensity to kill his own kind (shared to a limited degree with rats) may be attributed to his inability to adapt anachronistic patterns of survival (like primitive hunting) to his development of "civilizations" in which these patterns cannot be effectively sublimated. It may be attributed to other causes that have been suggested, such as a maladapted "territorial instinct," etc. Nevertheless, it exists and its social expression in war constitutes a biological control of his relationship to his natural environment that is peculiar to man alone.
War has served to help assure the survival of the human species. But as an evolutionary device to improve it, war is almost unbelievably inefficient. With few exceptions, the selective processes of other living creatures promote both specific survival and genetic improvement. When a conventionally adaptive animal faces one of its periodic crises of insufficiency, it is the "inferior" members of the species that normally disappear. An animal's social response to such a crisis may take the form of a mass migration, during which the weak fall by the wayside. Or it may follow the dramatic and more efficient pattern of lemming societies, in which the weaker members voluntarily disperse, leaving available food supplies for the stronger. In either case, the strong survive and the weak fall. In human societies, those who fight and die in wars for survival are in general its biologically stronger members. This is natural selection in reverse.
The regressive genetic effect of war has been often noted [25] and equally often deplored, even when it confuses biological and cultural factors. [26] The disproportionate loss of the biologically stronger remains inherent in traditional warfare. It serves to underscore the fact that survival of the species, rather than its improvement, is the fundamental purpose of natural selection, if it can be said to have a purpose, just as it is the basic premise of this study.
But as the polemologist Gaston Bouthoul [27] has pointed out, other institutions that were developed to serve this ecological function have proved even less satisfactory. (They include such established forms as these: infanticide, practiced chiefly in ancient and primitive societies; sexual mutilation; monasticism; forced emigration; extensive capital punishment, as in old China and eighteenth-century England; and other similar, usually localized, practices.)
Man's ability to increase his productivity of the essentials of physical life suggests that the need for protection against cyclical famine may be nearly obsolete. [28] It has thus tended to reduce the apparent importance of the basic ecological function of war, which is generally disregarded by peace theorists. Two aspects of it remain especially relevant, however. The first is obvious: current rates of population growth, compounded by environmental threat of chemical and other contaminants, may well bring about a new crisis of insufficiency. If so, it is likely to be one of unprecedented global magnitude, not merely regional or temporary. Conventional methods of warfare would almost surely prove inadequate, in this event, to reduce the consuming population to a level consistent with survival of the species.
The second relevant factor is the efficiency of modern methods of mass destruction. Even if their use is not required to meet a world population crisis, they offer, perhaps paradoxically, the first opportunity in the history of man to halt the regressive genetic effects of natural selection by war. Nuclear weapons are indiscriminate. Their application would bring to an end the disproportionate destruction of the physically stronger members of the species (the "warriors") in periods of war. Whether this prospect of genetic gain would offset the unfavorable mutations anticipated from postnuclear radioactivity we have not yet determined. What gives the question a bearing on our study is the possibility that the determination may yet have to be made.
Another secondary ecological trend bearing on projected population growth is the regressive effect of certain medical advances. Pestilence, for example, is no longer an important factor in population control. The problem of increased life expectancy has been aggravated. These advances also pose a potentially more sinister problem, in that undesirable genetic traits that were formally self-liquidating are now medically maintained. Many diseases that were once fatal at preprocreational ages are now cured; the effect of this development is to perpetuate undesirable susceptibilities and mutations. It seems clear that a new quasi-eugenic function of war is now in process of formation that will have to be taken into account in any transition plan. For the time being, the Department of Defense appears to have recognized such factors, as has been demonstrated by the planning under way by the Rand Corporation to cope with the breakdown in the ecological balance anticipated after a thermonuclear war. The Department has also begun to stockpile birds, for example, against the expected proliferation of radiation-resistant insects, etc.
The declared order of values in modern societies gives a high place
to the so-call "creative" activities, and an even higher one to those associated
with the advance of scientific knowledge. Widely held social values can
be translated into political equivalents, which in turn may bear on the
nature of a transition to peace. The attitudes of those who hold these
values must be taken into account in the planning of the transition. The
dependence, therefore, of cultural and scientific achievement on the war
system would be an important consideration in a transition plan even if
such achievement had no inherently necessary social function.
Of all the countless dichotomies invented by scholars to account for
the major differences in art styles and cycles, only one has been consistently
unambiguous in its application to a variety of forms and cultures. However
it may be verbalized, the basic distinction is this: Is the work war-oriented
or is it not? Among primitive peoples, the war dance is the most important
art form. Elsewhere, literature, music, painting, sculpture, and architecture
that has won lasting acceptance has invariably dealt with a theme of war,
expressly or implicitly, and has expressed the centricity of war to society.
The war in question may be national conflict, as in Shakespeare's plays,
Beethoven's music, or Goya's paintings, or it may be reflected in the form
of religious, social, or moral struggle, as in the work of Dante, Rembrandt,
and Bach. Art that cannot be classified as war-oriented is usually described
as "sterile," "decadent," and so on. Application of the "war standard"
to works of art may often leave room for debate in individual cases, but
there is no question of its role as the fundamental determinant of cultural
values. Aesthetic and moral standards have a common anthropological origin,
in the exaltation of bravery, the willingness to kill and risk death in
tribal warfare.
It is also instructive to note that the character of a society's culture
has borne a close relationship to its war-making potential, in the context
of its times. It is no accident that the current "cultural explosion" in
the United States is taking place during an era marked by an unusually
rapid advance in weaponry. This relationship is more generally recognized
than the literature on the subject would suggest. For example, many artists
and writers are now beginning to express concern over the limited creative
options they envisage in the warless world they think, or hope, may be
soon upon us. They are currently preparing for this possibility by unprecedented
experimentation with meaningless forms; their interest in recent years
has been increasingly engaged by the abstract pattern, the gratuitous emotion,
the random happening, and the unrelated sequence.
The relationship of war to scientific research and discovery is more
explicit. War is the principal motivational force for the development of
science at every level, from the abstractly conceptual to the narrowly
technological. Modern society places a high value on "pure" science, but
it is historically inescapable that all the significant discoveries that
have been made about the natural world have been inspired by the real or
imaginary military necessities of their epochs. The consequences of the
discoveries have indeed gone far afield, but war has always provided the
basic incentive.
Beginning with the development of iron and steel, and proceeding through
the discoveries of the laws of motion and thermodynamics to the age of
the atomic particle, the synthetic polymer, and the space capsule, no important
scientific advance has not been at least indirectly initiated by an implicit
requirement of weaponry. More prosaic examples include the transistor radio
(an outgrowth of military communications requirements), the assembly line
(from Civil War firearms needs), the steel-frame building (from the steel
battleship), the canal lock, and so on. A typical adaptation can be seen
in a device as modest as the common lawnmower; it developed from the revolving
scythe devised by Leonardo da Vinci to precede a horse-powered vehicle
into enemy ranks.
The most direct relationship can be found in medical technology. For
example, a giant "walking machine," an amplifier of body motions invented
for military use in difficult terrain, is now making it possible for many
previously confined to wheelchairs to walk. The Vietnam war alone has led
to spectacular improvements in amputation procedures, blood-handling techniques,
and surgical logistics. It has stimulated new large-scale research on malaria
and other tropical parasitic diseases; it is hard to estimate how long
this work would otherwise have been delayed, despite its enormous nonmilitary
importance to nearly half the world's population.
We have elected to omit from our discussion of the nonmilitary functions
of war those we do not consider critical to a transition program. This
is not to say they are unimportant, however, but only that they appear
to present no special problems for the organization of a peace-oriented
social system. They include the following:
War as a general social release. This is a psychosocial
function, serving the same purpose for a society as do the holiday, the
celebration, and the orgy for the individual - the release and redistribution
of undifferentiated tensions. War provides for the periodic necessary readjustment
of standards of social behavior (the "moral climate") and for the dissipation
of general boredom, one of the most consistently undervalued and unrecognized
of social phenomena.
War as a generational stabilizer. This psychological function,
served by other behavior patterns in other animals, enables the physically
deteriorating older generation to maintain its control of the younger,
destroying it if necessary.
War as an ideological clarifier. The dualism that characterizes
the traditional dialectic of all branches of philosophy and of stable political
relationships stems from war as the prototype of conflict. Except for secondary
considerations, there cannot be, to put it as simply as possible, more
than two sides to a question because there cannot be more than two sides
to a war.
War as the basis for international understanding. Before
the development of modern communications, the strategic requirements of
war provided the only substantial incentive for the enrichment of one national
culture with the achievements of another. Although this is still the case
in many international relationships, the function is obsolescent.
We have also foregone extended characterization of those functions we
assume to be widely and explicitly recognized. An obvious example is the
role of war as controller of the quality and degree of unemployment. This
is more than an economic and political subfunction; its sociological, cultural,
and ecological aspects are also important, although often teleonomic. But
none affect the general problem of substitution. The same is true of certain
other functions; those we have included are sufficient to define the scope
of the problem.
By now it should be clear that the most detailed and comprehensive master
plan for a transition to world peace will remain academic if it fails to
deal forthrightly with the problem of the critical nonmilitary functions
of war. The social needs they serve are essential; if the war system no
longer exists to meet them, substitute institutions will have to be established
for the purpose. These surrogates must be "realistic," which is to say
of a scope and nature that can be conceived and implemented in the context
of present-day social capabilities. This is not the truism it may appear
to be; the requirements of radical social change often reveal the distinction
between a most conservative projection and a wildly utopian scheme to be
fine indeed.
In this section we will consider some possible substitutes for these
functions. Only in rare instances have they been put forth for the purposes
which concern us here, but we see no reason to limit ourselves to proposals
that address themselves explicitly to the problem as we have outlined it.
We will disregard the ostensible, or military, functions of war; it is
a premise of this study that the transition to peace implies absolutely
that they will no longer exist in any relevant sense. We will also disregard
the noncritical functions exemplified at the end of the preceding section.
Economic surrogates for war must meet two principal criteria. They must
be "wasteful," in the common sense of the word, and they must operate outside
the normal supply-demand system. A corollary that should be obvious is
that the magnitude of the waste must be sufficient to meet the needs of
a particular society. An economy as advanced and complex as our own requires
the planned average annual destruction of not less than 10 percent of gross
national product [29] if it is effectively to fulfill
its stabilizing function. When the mass of a balance wheel is inadequate
to the power it is intended to control, its effect can be self-defeating,
as with a runaway locomotive. The analogy, though crude, [30]
is especially apt for the American economy, as our record of cyclical depressions
shows. All have taken place during periods of grossly inadequate military
spending.
Those few economic conversion programs which by implication acknowledge
the nonmilitary economic function of war (at least to some extent) tend
to assume that so-called social-welfare expenditures will fill the vacuum
created by the disappearance of military spending. When one considers the
backlog of unfinished business - proposed but still unexecuted - in this
field, the assumption seems plausible. Let us examine briefly the following
list, which is more or less typical of general social welfare programs.
[31]
Health. Drastic expansion of medical research, education,
and training facilities; hospital and clinic construction; the general
objective of complete government-guaranteed health care for
all, at a level consistent with current developments in medical technology.
Education. The equivalent of the foregoing in teacher
training; schools and libraries; the drastic upgrading of standards, with
the general objective of making available for all an attainable educational
goal equivalent to what is now considered a professional degree.
Housing. Clean, comfortable, safe, and spacious living
space for all, at the level now enjoyed by about 15 percent of the population
in this country (less in most others).
Transportation. The establishment of a system of mass
public transportation making it possible for all to travel to and from
areas of work and recreation quickly, comfortably, and conveniently, and
to travel privately for pleasure rather than necessity.
Physical environment. The development and protection of
water supplies, forests, parks, and other natural resources; the elimination
of chemical and bacterial contaminants from air, water, and soil.
Poverty. The genuine elimination of poverty, defined by
a standard consistent with current economic productivity, by means of guaranteed
annual income or whatever system of distribution will best assure its achievement.
This is only a sampler of the more obvious domestic social welfare items,
and we have listed it in a deliberately broad, perhaps extravagant, manner.
In the past, such a vague and ambitious-sounding "program" wold have been
dismissed out of hand, without serious consideration; it would clearly
have been, prima facie, far too costly, quite apart from
its political implications. [32] Our objection to it,
on the other hand, could hardly be more contradictory. As an economic substitute
for war, it is inadequate because it would be far too cheap.
If this seems paradoxical, it must be remembered that up to now all
proposed social-welfare expenditures have had to be measured within
the war economy, not as a replacement for it. The old slogan about a battleship
or an ICBM costing as much as x hospitals or y
schools or z homes takes on a very different meaning if there
are to be no more battleships or ICBM's.
Since the list is general, we have elected to forestall the tangential
controversy that surrounds arbitrary cost projections by offering no individual
cost estimates. But the maximum program that could be physically effected
along the lines indicated could approach the established level of military
spending only for a limited time - in our opinion, subject to a detailed
cost-and-feasibility analysis, less than ten years. In this short period,
at this rate, the major goals of the program would have been achieved.
Its capital-investment phase would have been completed, and it would have
established a permanent comparatively modest level of annual operating
cost - within the framework of the general economy.
Here is the basic weakness of the social-welfare surrogate. On the short-term
basis, a maximum program of this sort could replace a normal military spending
program, provided it was designed, like the military model, to be subject
to arbitrary control. Public housing starts, for example, or the development
of modern medical centers might be accelerated or halted from time to time,
as the requirements of a stable economy might dictate. But on the long-term
basis, social-welfare spending, no matter how often redefined, would necessarily
become an integral, accepted part of the economy, of no more value as a
stabilizer than the automobile industry or old age and survivors' insurance.
Apart from whatever merit social-welfare programs are deemed to have for
their own sake, their function as a substitute for war in the economy would
thus be self-liquidating. They might serve, however, as expedients pending
the development of more durable substitute measures.
Another economic surrogate that has been proposed is a series of giant
"space research" programs. These have already demonstrated their utility
in more modest scale within the military economy. What has been implied,
although not yet expressly put forth, is the development of a long-range
sequence of space-research projects with largely unattainable goals. This
kind of program offers several advantages lacking in the social welfare
model. First, it is unlikely to phase itself out, regardless of the predictable
"surprises" science has in store for us: the universe is too big. In the
event some individual project unexpectedly succeeds there would be no dearth
of substitute problems. For example, if colonization of the moon proceeds
on schedule, it could then become "necessary" to establish a beachhead
on Mars or Jupiter, and so on. Second, it need be no more dependent on
the general supply-demand economy than its military prototype. Third, it
lends itself extraordinarily well to arbitrary control.
Space research can be viewed as the nearest modern equivalent yet devised
to the pyramid-building, and similar ritualistic enterprises, of ancient
societies. It is true that the scientific value of the space program, even
of what has already been accomplished, is substantial on its own terms.
But current programs are absurdly and obviously disproportionate, in the
relationship of the knowledge sought to the expenditures committed. All
but a small fraction of the space budget, measured by the standards of
comparable scientific objectives, must be charged de facto
to the military economy. Future space research, projected as a war surrogate,
would further reduce the the "scientific" rationale of its budget to a
minuscule percentage indeed. As a purely economic substitute for war, therefore,
extension of the space program warrants serious consideration.
In Section 3 we pointed out that certain disarmament
models, which we called conservative, postulated extremely expensive and
elaborate inspection systems. Would it be possible to extend and institutionalize
such systems to the point where they might serve as economic surrogates
for war spending? The organization of failsafe inspection machinery could
well be ritualized in a manner similar to that of established military
processes. "Inspection teams" might be very like armies, and their technical
equipment might be very like weapons. Inflating the inspection budget to
military scale presents no difficulty. The appeal of this kind of scheme
lies in the comparative ease of transition between two parallel systems.
The "elaborate inspection" surrogate is fundamentally fallacious, however.
Although it might be economically useful, as well as politically necessary,
during the disarmament transition, it would fail as a substitute for the
economic function of war for one simple reason. Peacekeeping inspection
is part of a war system, not of a peace system. It implies the possibility
of weapons maintenance or manufacture, which could not exist in a world
at peace as here defined. Massive inspection also implies sanctions, and
thus war-readiness.
The same fallacy is more obvious in plans to create a patently useless
"defense conversion" apparatus. The long-discredited proposal to build
"total" civil defense facilities is one example; another is the plan to
establish a giant antimissile missile complex (Nike-X, et al.).
These programs, of course, are economic rather than strategic. Nevertheless,
they are not substitutes for military spending but merely different forms
of it.
A more sophisticated variant is the proposal to establish the "Unarmed
Forces" of the United States. [33] This would conveniently
maintain the entire institutional military structure, redirecting it essentially
toward social-welfare activities on a global scale. It would be, in effect,
a giant military Peace Corps. There is nothing inherently unworkable about
this plan, and using the existing military system to effectuate its own
demise is both ingenious and convenient. But even on a greatly magnified
world basis, social-welfare expenditures must sooner or later reenter the
atmosphere of the normal economy. The practical transitional virtues of
such a scheme would thus be eventually negated by its inadequacy as a permanent
economic stabilizer. The war system makes the stable government of societies possible. It
does this essentially by providing an external necessity for a society
to accept political rule. In so doing, it establishes the basis for nationhood
and the authority of government to control its constituents. What other
institution or combination of programs might serve these functions in its
place?
We have already pointed out that the end of war means the end of national
sovereignty, and thus the end of nationhood as we know it today. But this
does not necessarily mean the end of nations in the administrative sense,
and internal political power will remain essential to a stable society.
The emerging "nations" of the peace epoch must continue to draw political
authority from some source.
A number of proposals have been made governing the relations between
nations after total disarmament; all are basically juridical in nature.
They contemplate institutions more or less like a World Court, or a United
Nations, but vested with real authority. They may or may not serve their
ostensible postmilitary purpose of settling international disputes, but
we need not discuss that here. None would offer effective external pressure
on a peace-world nation to organize itself politically.
It might be argued that a well-armed international police force, operating
under the authority of such a supranational "court," could well serve the
function of external enemy. This, however, would constitute a military
operation, like the inspection schemes mentioned, and, like them, would
be inconsistent with the premise of an end to the war system. It is possible
that a variant of the "Unarmed Forces" idea might be developed in such
a way that its "constructive" (i.e., social welfare) activities could be
combined with an economic "threat" of sufficient size and credibility to
warrant political organization. Would this kind of threat also be contradictory
to our central premise? - that is, would it be inevitably military? Not
necessarily, in our view, but we are skeptical of its capacity to evoke
credibility. Also, the obvious destabilizing effect of any global social
welfare surrogate on politically necessary class relationships would create
an entirely new set of transition problems at least equal in magnitude.
Credibility, in fact, lies at the heart of the problem of developing
a political substitute for war. This is where the space-race proposals,
in many ways so well suited as economic substitutes for war, fall short.
The most ambitious and unrealistic space project cannot of itself generate
a believable external menace. It has been hotly argued [34]
that such a menace would offer the "last, best hope of peace," etc., by
uniting mankind against the danger of destruction by "creatures" from other
planets or from outer space. Experiments have been proposed to test the
credibility of an out-of-our-world invasion threat; it is possible that
a few of the more difficult-to-explain "flying saucer" incidents of recent
years were in fact early experiments of this kind. If so, they could hardly
have been judged encouraging. We anticipate no difficulties in making a
"need" for a giant super space program credible for economic purposes,
even were there not ample precedent; extending it, for political purposes,
to include features unfortunately associated with science fiction would
obviously be a more dubious undertaking.
Nevertheless, an effective political substitute for war would require
"alternate enemies," some of which might seem equally farfetched in the
context of the current war system. It may be, for instance, that gross
pollution of the environment can eventually replace the possibility of
mass destruction by nuclear weapons as the principal apparent threat to
the survival of the species. Poisoning of the air, and of the principal
sources of food and water supply, is already well advanced, and at first
glance would seem promising in this respect; it constitutes a threat that
can be dealt with only through social organization and political power.
But from present indications it will be a generation to a generation and
a half before environmental pollution, however severe, will be sufficiently
menacing, on a global scale, to offer a possible basis for a solution.
It is true that the rate of pollution could be increased selectively
for this purpose; in fact, the mere modifying of existing programs for
the deterrence of pollution could speed up the process enough to make the
threat credible much sooner. But the pollution problem has been so widely
publicized in recent years that it seems highly improbable that a program
of deliberate environmental poisoning could be implemented in a politically
acceptable manner.
However unlikely some of the possible alternate enemies we have mentioned
may seem, we must emphasize that one must be found, of credible
quality and magnitude, if a transition to peace is ever to come about without
social disintegration. It is more probable, in our judgment, that such
a threat will have to be invented, rather than developed from unknown conditions.
For this reason, we believe further speculation about its putative nature
ill-advised in this context. Since there is considerable doubt, in our
minds, that any viable political surrogate can be devised,
we are reluctant to compromise, by premature discussion, any possible option
that may eventually lie open to our government.
Most proposals that address themselves, explicitly or otherwise, to
the postwar problem of controlling the socially alienated turn to some
variant of the Peace Corps or the so-called Job Corps for a solution. The
socially disaffected, the economically unprepared, the psychologically
unconformable, the hard-core "delinquents," the incorrigible "subversives,"
and the rest of the unemployable are seen as somehow transformed by the
disciplines of a service modeled on military precedent into more or less
dedicated social service workers. This presumption also informs the otherwise
hardheaded ratiocination of the "Unarmed Forces" plan.
The problem has been addressed, in the language of popular sociology,
by Secretary McNamara. "Even in our abundant societies, we have reason
enough to worry over the tensions that coil and tighten among underprivileged
young people, and finally flail out in delinquency and crime. What are
we to expect ... where mounting frustrations are likely to fester into
eruptions of violence and extremism?" In a seemingly unrelated passage,
he continues:
It seems clear that Mr. McNamara and other proponents of the peace-corps
surrogate for this war function lean heavily on the success of the paramilitary
Depression programs mentioned in the last section. We find the precedent
wholly inadequate in degree. Neither the lack of relevant precedent, however,
nor the dubious social-welfare sentimentality characterizing this approach
warrant its rejection without careful study. It may be viable - provided,
first, that the military origin of the Corps format be effectively rendered
out of its operational activity, and second, that the transition from paramilitary
activities to "developmental work" can be effected without regard to the
attitudes of the Corps personnel or to the "value" of the work it is expected
to perform.
Another possible surrogate for the control of potential enemies of society
is the reintroduction, in some form consistent with modern technology and
political processes, of slavery. Up to now, this has been suggested only
in fiction, notably in the works of Wells, Huxley, Orwell, and others engaged
in the imaginative anticipation of the sociology of the future. But the
fantasies projected in Brave New World and 1984
have seemed less and less implausible over the years since their publication.
The traditional association of slavery with ancient preindustrial cultures
should not blind us to its adaptability to advanced forms of social organization,
nor should its equally traditional incompatibility with Western moral and
economic values. It is entirely possible that the development of a sophisticated
form of slavery may be an absolute prerequisite for social control in a
world at peace. As a practical matter, conversion of the code of military
discipline to a euphemized form of enslavement would entail surprisingly
little revision; the logical first step would be the adoption of some form
of "universal" military service.
When it comes to postulating a credible substitute for war capable of
directing human behavior patterns in behalf of social organization, few
options suggest themselves. Like its political function, the motivational
function of war requires the existence of a genuinely menacing social enemy.
The principal difference is that for purposes of motivating basic allegiance,
as distinct from accepting political authority, the "alternate enemy" must
imply a more immediate, tangible, and directly felt threat of destruction.
It must justify the need for taking and paying a "blood price" in wide
areas of human concern.
In this respect, the possible substitute enemies noted earlier would
be insufficient. One exception might be the environmental-pollution model,
if the danger to society it posed was genuinely imminent. The fictive models
would have to carry the weight of extraordinary conviction, underscored
with a not inconsiderable actual sacrifice of life; the construction of
an up-to-date mythological or religious structure for this purpose would
present difficulties in our era, but must certainly be considered.
Games theorists have suggested, in other contexts, the development of
"blood games" for the effective control of individual aggressive impulses.
It is an ironic commentary on the current state of war and peace studies
that it was left not to scientists but to the makers of a commercial film
[36] to develop a model for this notion, on the implausible
level of popular melodrama, as a ritualized manhunt. More realistically,
such a ritual might be socialized, in the manner of the Spanish Inquisition
and the less formal witch trials of other periods, for purposes of "social
purification," "state security," or other rationale both acceptable and
credible to postwar societies. The feasibility of such an updated version
of still another ancient institution, though doubtful, is considerably
less fanciful than the wishful notion of many peace planners that a lasting
condition of peace can be brought about without the most painstaking examination
of every possible surrogate for the essential functions of war. What is
involved here, in a sense, is the quest for William James's "moral equivalent
of war."
It is also possible that the two functions considered under this heading
may be jointly served, in the sense of establishing the antisocial, for
whom a control institution is needed, as the "alternate enemy" needed to
hold society together. The relentless and irreversible advance of unemployability
at all levels of society, and the similar extension of generalized alienation
from accepted values [37] may make some such program
necessary even as an adjunct to the war system. As before, we will not
speculate on the specific forms this kind of program might take, except
to note that there is again ample precedent, in the treatment meted out
to disfavored, allegedly menacing, ethnic groups in certain societies during
historical periods. [38] Considering the the shortcomings of war as a mechanism of selective
population control, it might appear that devising substitutes for this
function should be comparatively simple. Schematically this so, but the
problem of timing the transition to a new ecological balancing device makes
the feasibility of substitution less certain.
It must be remembered that the limitation of war in this function is
entirely eugenic. War has not been genetically progressive. But as a system
of gross population control to preserve the species it cannot fairly be
faulted. And, as has been pointed out, the nature of war is itself in transition.
Current trends in warfare - the increased strategic bombing of civilians
and the greater military importance now attached to the destruction of
sources of supply (as opposed to purely "military" bases and personnel)
- strongly suggest that a truly qualitative improvement is in the making.
Assuming the war system is to continue, it is more than probable that the
regressively selective quality of war will have been reversed, as its victims
become more genetically representative of their societies.
There is no question but that a universal requirement that procreation
be limited to the products of artificial insemination would provide a fully
adequate substitute control for population levels. Such a reproductive
system would, of course, have the added advantage of being susceptible
of direct eugenic management. Its predictable further development - conception
and embryonic growth taking place wholly under laboratory conditions -
would extend these controls to their logical conclusion. The ecological
function of war under these circumstances would not only be superseded
but surpassed in effectiveness.
The indicated intermediate step - total control of conception with a
variant of the ubiquitous "pill," via water supplies or certain essential
foodstuffs, offset by a controlled "antidote" - is already under development.
[39] There would appear to be no foreseeable need to
revert to any of the outmoded practices referred to in the previous section
(infanticide, etc.) as there might have been if the possibility of transition
to peace had arisen two generations ago.
The real question here, therefore, does not concern the viability of
this war substitute, but the political problems involved in bringing it
about. It cannot be established while the war system is still in effect.
The reason for this is simple: excess population is war material. As long
as any society must contemplate even a remote possibility of war, it must
maintain a maximum supportable population, even when so doing critically
aggravates an economic liability. This is paradoxical, in view of war's
role in reducing excess population, but it is readily understood. War controls
the general population level, but the ecological interest
of any single society lies in maintaining its hegemony vis-a-vis other
societies. The obvious analogy can be seen in any free-enterprise economy.
Practices damaging to the society as a whole - both competitive and monopolistic
- are abetted by the conflicting economic motives of individual capital
interests. The obvious precedent can be found in the seemingly irrational
political difficulties which have blocked universal adoption of simple
birth-control methods. Nations desperately in need of increasing unfavorable
production-consumption ratios are nevertheless unwilling to gamble their
possible military requirements of twenty years hence for this purpose.
Unilateral population control, as practiced in ancient Japan and in other
isolated societies, is out of the question in today's world.
Since the eugenic solution cannot be achieved until the transition to
the peace system takes place, why not wait? One must qualify the inclination
to agree. As we noted earlier, a real possibility of an unprecedented global
crisis of insufficiency exists today, which the war system may not be able
to forestall. If this should come to pass before an agreed-upon transition
to peace were completed, the result might be irrevocably disastrous. There
is clearly no solution to this dilemma; it is a risk which must be taken.
But it tends to support the view that if a decision is made to eliminate
the war system, it were better done sooner than later. Strictly speaking, the function of war as the determinant of cultural
values and as the prime mover of scientific progress may not be critical
in a world without war. Our criterion for the basic nonmilitary functions
of war has been: Are they necessary to the survival and stability of society?
The absolute need for substitute cultural value-determinants and for the
continued advance of scientific knowledge is not established. We believe
it important, however, in behalf of those for whom these functions hold
subjective significance, that it be known what they can reasonably expect
in culture and science after a transition to peace.
So far as the creative arts are concerned, there is no reason to believe
they would disappear, but only that they would change in character and
relative social importance. The elimination of war would in due course
deprive them of their principal conative force, but it would necessarily
take some time for the effect of this withdrawal to be felt. During the
transition, and perhaps for a generation thereafter, themes of sociomoral
conflict inspired by the war system would be increasingly transferred to
the idiom of purely personal sensibility. At the same time, a new aesthetic
would have to develop. Whatever its name, form, or rationale, its function
would be to express, in language appropriate to the new period, the once
discredited philosophy that art exists for its own sake. This aesthetic
would reject unequivocally the classic requirement of paramilitary conflict
as the substantive content of great art. The eventual effect of the peace-world
philosophy of art would be democratizing in the extreme, in the sense that
a generally acknowledged subjectivity of artistic standards would equalize
their new, content-free "values."
What may be expected to happen is that art would be reassigned the role
it once played in a few primitive peace-oriented systems. This was the
function of pure decoration, entertainment, or play, entirely free of the
burden of expressing the sociomoral values and conflicts of a war-oriented
society. It is interesting that the groundwork for such a value-free aesthetic
is already being laid today, in growing experimentation in art without
content, perhaps in anticipation of a world without conflict. A cult has
developed around a new kind of cultural determinism, [40]
which proposes that the technological form of a cultural expression determines
its values rather than does its ostensibly meaningful content. Its clear
implication is that there is no "good" or "bad" art, only that which is
appropriate to its (technological) times and that which is not. Its cultural
effect has been to promote circumstantial constructions and unplanned expressions;
it denies to art the relevance of sequential logic. Its significance in
this context is that it provides a working model of one kind of value-free
culture we might reasonably anticipate in a world at peace.
So far as science is concerned, it might appear at first glance that
a giant space-research program, the most promising among the proposed economic
surrogates for war, might also serve as the basic stimulator of scientific
research. The lack of fundamental organized social conflict inherent in
space work, however, would rule it out as an adequate motivational substitute
for war when applied to "pure" science. But it could no doubt sustain the
broad range of technological activity that a space budget
of military dimensions would require. A similarly scaled social-welfare
program could provide a comparable impetus to low-keyed technological advances,
especially in medicine, rationalized construction methods, educational
psychology, etc. The eugenic substitute for the ecological function of
war would also require continuing research in certain areas of the life
sciences.
Apart from these partial substitutes for war, it must be kept in mind
that the momentum given to scientific progress by the great wars of the
past century, and even more by the anticipation of World War III, is intellectually
and materially enormous. It is our finding that if the war system were
to end tomorrow this momentum is so great that the pursuit of scientific
knowledge could reasonably be expected to go forward without noticeable
diminution for perhaps two decades. [41] It would then
continue, at a progressively decreasing tempo, for at least another two
decades before the "bank account" of today's unresolved problems would
become exhausted. By the standards of the questions we have learned to
ask today, there would no longer be anything worth knowing still unknown;
we cannot conceive, by definition, of the scientific questions to ask once
those we can not comprehend are answered.
This leads unavoidably to another matter: the intrinsic value of the
unlimited search for knowledge. We of course offer no independent value
judgments here, but it is germane to point out that a substantial minority
of scientific opinion feels that search to be circumscribed in any case.
This opinion is itself a factor in considering the need for a substitute
for the scientific function of war. For the record, we must also take note
of the precedent that during long periods of human history, often covering
thousands of years, in which no intrinsic social value was assigned to
scientific progress, stable societies did survive and flourish. Although
this could not have been possible in the modern industrial world, we cannot
be certain it may not again be true in a future world at peace.
War is not, as is widely assumed, primarily an instrument of policy
utilized by nations to extend or defend their expressed political values
or their economic interests. On the contrary, it is itself the principal
basis of organization on which all modern societies are constructed. The
common proximate cause of war is the apparent interference of one nation
with the aspirations of another. But at the root of all ostensible differences
of national interest lie the dynamic requirements of the war system itself
for periodic armed conflict. Readiness for war characterizes contemporary
social systems more broadly than their economic and political structures,
which it subsumes.
Economic analyses of the anticipated problems of transition to peace
have not recognized the broad preeminence of war in the definition of social
systems. The same is true, with rare and only partial exceptions, of model
disarmament "scenarios." For this reason, the value of this previous work
is limited to the mechanical aspects of transition. Certain features of
these models may perhaps be applicable to a real situation of conversion
to peace; this will depend on their compatibility with a substantive, rather
than a procedural, peace plan. Such a plan can be developed only from the
premise of full understanding of the nature of the war system it proposes
to abolish, which in turn presupposes detailed comprehension of the functions
the war system performs for society. It will require the construction of
a detailed and feasible system of substitutes for those functions that
are necessary to the stability and survival of human societies.
The Functions of War
The visible, military function of war requires no elucidation; it is
not only obvious but also irrelevant to a transition to the condition of
peace, in which it will by definition be superfluous. It is also subsidiary
in social significance to the implied, nonmilitary functions of war; those
critical to transition can be summarized in five principal groupings.
1. Economic. War has provided both ancient and
modern societies with a dependable system for stabilizing and controlling
national economies. No alternate method of control has yet been tested
in a complex modern economy that has shown itself remotely comparable in
scope or effectiveness.
2. Political. The permanent possibility of war
is the foundation for stable government; it supplies the basis for general
acceptance of political authority. It has enabled societies to maintain
necessary class distinctions, and it has ensured the subordination of the
citizen to the state, by virtue of the residual war powers inherent in
the concept of nationhood. No modern political ruling group has successfully
controlled its constituency after failing to sustain the continuing credibility
of an external threat of war.
3. Sociological. War, through the medium of military institutions,
has uniquely served societies, throughout the course of known history,
as an indispensable controller of dangerous social dissidence and destructive
antisocial tendencies. As the most formidable of threats to life itself,
and as the only one susceptible to mitigation by social organization alone,
it has played another equally fundamental role: the war system has provided
the machinery through which the motivational forces governing human behavior
have been translated into binding social allegiance. It has thus ensured
the degree of social cohesion necessary to the viability of nations. No
other institution, or group of institutions, in modern societies, has successfully
served these functions.
4. Ecological. War has been the principal evolutionary
device for maintaining a satisfactory ecological balance between gross
human population and supplies available for its survival. It is unique
to the human species.
5. Cultural and Scientific. War-orientation has determined
the basic standards of value in the creative arts, and has provided the
fundamental motivational source of scientific and technological progress.
The concepts that the arts express values independent of their own forms
and that the successful pursuit of knowledge has intrinsic social value
have long been accepted in modern societies; the development of the arts
and sciences during this period has been corollary to the parallel development
of weaponry.
Substitutes for the Functions of War: Criteria
The foregoing functions of war are essential to the survival of the
social systems we know today. With two possible exceptions they are also
essential to any kind of stable social organization that might survive
in a warless world. Discussion of the ways and means of transition to such
a world are meaningless unless a) substitute institutions can be devised
to fill these functions, or b) it can reasonably be hypothecated that the
loss or partial loss of any one function need not destroy the viability
of future societies.
Such substitute institutions and hypotheses must meet varying criteria.
In general, they must be technically feasible, politically acceptable,
and potentially credible to the members of the societies that adopt them.
Specifically, they must be characterized as follows:
1. Economic. An acceptable economic surrogate for the
war system will require the expenditure of resources for completely nonproductive
purposes at a level comparable to that of the military expenditures otherwise
demanded by the size and complexity of each society. Such a substitute
system of apparent "waste" must be of a nature that will permit it to remain
independent of the normal supply-demand economy; it must be subject to
arbitrary political control.
2. Political. A viable political substitute for war must
posit a generalized external menace to each society of a nature and degree
sufficient to require the organization and acceptance of political authority.
3. Sociological. First, in the permanent absence of war,
new institutions must be developed that will effectively control the socially
destructive segments of societies. Second, for purposes of adapting the
physical and psychological dynamics of human behavior to the needs of social
organization, a credible substitute for war must generate an omnipresent
and readily understood fear of personal destruction. This fear must be
of a nature and degree sufficient to ensure adherence to societal values
to the full extent that they are acknowledged to transcend the value of
an individual human life.
4. Ecological. A substitute for war in its function
as the uniquely human system of population control must ensure the survival,
if not necessarily the improvement, of the species, in terms of its relation
to environmental supply.
5. Cultural and Scientific. A surrogate for the
function of war as the determinant of cultural values must establish a
basis of sociomoral conflict of equally compelling force and scope. A substitute
motivational basis for the quest for scientific knowledge must be similarly
informed by a comparable sense of internal necessity.
Substitutes for the Functions of War: Models
The following substitute institutions, among others, have been proposed
for consideration as replacements for the nonmilitary functions of war.
That they may not have been originally set forth for that purpose does
not preclude or invalidate their possible application here.
1. Economic. a) A comprehensive social-welfare program,
directed toward maximum improvement of general conditions of human life.
b) A giant open-end space research program, aimed at unreachable targets.
c) A permanent, ritualized, ultra-elaborate disarmament inspection system,
and variants of such a system.
2. Political. a) An omnipresent, virtually omnipotent
international police force. b) An established and recognized extraterrestrial
menace. c) Massive global environmental pollution. d) Fictitious alternate
enemies.
3. Sociological: Control function. a) Programs generally
derived from the Peace Corps model. b) A modern, sophisticated form of
slavery. Motivational function. a) Intensified environmental
pollution. b) New religious or other mythologies. c) Socially oriented
blood games. d) Combination forms.
4. Ecological. A comprehensive program of applied eugenics.
5. Cultural. No replacement institution offered.
Scientific. The secondary requirements of the space research,
social welfare, and/or eugenics programs.
Substitutes for the Functions of War: Evaluation
The models listed above reflect only the beginning of the quest for
substitute institutions for the functions of war, rather than a recapitulation
of alternatives. It would be both premature and inappropriate, therefore,
to offer final judgments on their applicability to a transition to peace
and after. Furthermore, since the necessary but complex project of correlating
the compatibility of proposed surrogates for different functions could
be treated only in exemplary fashion at this time, we have elected to withhold
such hypothetical correlation as were tested as statistically inadequate.
[42]
Nevertheless, some tentative and cursory comments on these proposed
functional "solutions" will indicate the scope of the difficulties involved
in this area of peace planning.
Economic. The social-welfare model cannot be expected
to remain outside the normal economy after the conclusion of its predominantly
capital-investment phase; its value in this function can therefore be only
temporary. The space-research substitute appears to meet both major criteria,
and should be examined in greater detail, especially in respect to its
probable effects on other war functions. "Elaborate inspection" schemes,
although superficially attractive, are inconsistent with the basic premise
of transition to peace. The "unarmed forces" variant, logistically similar,
is subject to the same functional criticism as the general social-welfare
model.
Political. Like the inspection-scheme surrogates, proposals
for plenipotentiary international police are inherently incompatible with
the ending of the war system. The "unarmed forces" variant, amended to
include unlimited powers of economic sanction, might conceivably be expanded
to constitute a credible external menace. Development of an acceptable
threat from "outer space," presumably in conjunction with a space-research
surrogate for economic control, appears unpromising in terms of credibility.
The environmental-pollution model does not seem sufficiently responsive
to immediate social control, except through arbitrary acceleration of current
pollution trends; this in turn raises questions of political acceptability.
New, less regressive, approaches to the creation of fictitious global "enemies"
invite further investigation.
Ecological. The only apparent problem in the application
of an adequate eugenic substitute for war is that of timing; it cannot
be effectuated until the transition to peace has been completed, which
involves a serious temporary risk of ecological failure.
Cultural. No plausible substitute for this function of
war has yet been proposed. It may be, however, that a basic cultural value-determinant
is not necessary to the survival of a stable society. Scientific.
The same might be said for the function of war as the prime mover of the
search for knowledge. However, adoption of either a giant space-research
program, a comprehensive social-welfare program, or a master program of
eugenic control would provide motivation for limited technologies.
Until such a unified program is developed, at least hypothetically,
it is impossible for this or any other group to furnish meaningful answers
to the questions originally presented to us. When asked how best to prepare
for the advent of peace, we must first reply, as strongly as we can, that
the war system cannot responsibly be allowed to disappear until 1) we know
exactly what it is we plan to put in its place, and 2) we are certain,
beyond reasonable doubt, that these substitute institutions will serve
their purposes in terms of the survival and stability of society. It will
then be time enough to develop methods for effectuating the transition;
procedural programming must follow, not precede, substantive solutions.
Such solutions, if indeed they exist, will not be arrived at without
a revolutionary revision of the modes of thought heretofore considered
appropriate to peace research. That we have examined the fundamental questions
involved from a dispassionate, value-free point of view should not imply
that we do not appreciate the intellectual and emotional difficulties that
must be overcome on all decision-making levels before these questions are
generally acknowledged by others for what they are. They reflect, on an
intellectual level, traditional emotional resistance to new (more lethal
and thus more "shocking") forms of weaponry. The understated comment of
then-Senator Hubert Humphrey on the publication of On Thermonuclear
War is still very much to the point: "New thoughts, particularly
those which appear to contradict current assumptions, are always painful
for the mind to contemplate."
Nor, simply because we have not discussed them, do we minimize the massive
reconciliation of conflicting interest which domestic as well as international
agreement on proceeding toward genuine peace presupposes. This factor was
excluded from the purview of our assignment, but we would be remiss if
we failed to take it into account. Although no insuperable obstacle lies
in the path of reaching such general agreements, formidable short-term
private-group and general-class interest in maintaining the war system
is well established and widely recognized. The resistance to peace stemming
from such interest is only tangential, in the long run, to the basic functions
of war, but it will not be easily overcome, in this country or elsewhere.
Some observers, in fact, believe that it cannot be overcome at all in our
time, that the price of peace is, simply, too high. This bears on our overall
conclusions to the extent that timing in the transference to substitute
institutions may often be the critical factor in their political feasibility.
It is uncertain, at this time, whether peace will ever be possible.
It is far more questionable, by the objective standard of continued social
survival rather than that of emotional pacifism, that it would be desirable
even if it were demonstrably attainable. The war system, for all its subjective
repugnance to important sections of "public opinion," has demonstrated
its effectiveness since the beginning of recorded history; it has provided
the basis for the development of many impressively durable civilizations,
including that which is dominant today. It has consistently provided unambiguous
social priorities. It is, on the whole, a known quantity. A viable system
of peace, assuming that the great and complex questions of substitute institutions
raised in this Report are both soluble and solved, would still constitute
a venture into the unknown, with the inevitable risks attendant on the
unforeseen, however small and however well hedged.
Government decision-makers tend to choose peace over war whenever a
real option exists, because it usually appear to be the "safer" choice.
Under most immediate circumstances they are likely to be right. But in
terms of long-range social stability, the opposite is true. At our present
state of knowledge and reasonable inference, it is the war system that
must be identified with stability, the peace system with social speculation,
however justifiable the speculation may appear, in terms of subjective
moral or emotional values. A nuclear physicist once remarked, in respect
to a possible disarmament agreement: "If we could change the world into
a world in which no weapons could be made, that would be stabilizing. But
agreements we can expect with the Soviets would be destabilizing." [43]
The qualification and the bias are equally irrelevant; any
condition of genuine total peace, however achieved, would be destabilizing
until proved otherwise.
If it were necessary at this moment to opt irrevocably for the retention
or for the dissolution of the war system, common prudence would dictate
the former course. But it is not yet necessary, late as the hour appears.
And more factors must eventually enter the war-peace equation than even
the most determined search for alternative institutions for the functions
of war can be expected to reveal. One group of such factors has been given
only passing mention in this Report; it centers around the possible obsolescence
of the war system itself. We have noted, for instance, the limitations
of the war system in filling its ecological function and the declining
importance of this aspect of war. It by no means stretches the imagination
to visualize comparable developments which may compromise the efficacy
of war as, for example, an economic controller or as an organizer of social
allegiance. This kind of possibility, however remote, serves as a reminder
that all calculations of contingency not only involve the weighing of one
group of risks against another, but require a respectful allowance for
error on both sides of the scale.
A more expedient reason for pursuing the investigation of alternate
ways and means to serve the current functions of war is narrowly political.
It is possible that one or more major sovereign nations may arrive, through
ambiguous leadership, at a position in which a ruling administrative class
may lose control of basic public opinion or of its ability to rationalize
a desired war. It is not hard to imagine, in such circumstance, a situation
in which such governments may feel forced to initiate serious full-scale
disarmament proceedings (perhaps provoked by "accidental" nuclear explosions),
and that such negotiations may lead to the actual disestablishment of military
institutions. As our Report has made clear, this could be catastrophic.
It seems evident that, in the event an important part of the world is suddenly
plunged without sufficient warning into an inadvertent peace, even partial
and inadequate preparation for the possibility may be better than none.
The difference could even be critical. The models considered in the preceding
chapter, both those that seem promising and those that do not, have one
positive feature in common - an inherent flexibility of phasing. And despite
our strictures against knowingly proceeding into peace-transition procedures
without thorough substantive preparation, our government must nevertheless
be ready to move in this direction with whatever limited resources of planning
are on hand at the time - if circumstances so require. An arbitrary all-or-nothing
approach is no more realistic in the development of contingency peace programming
than it is anywhere else.
But the principal cause for concern over the continuing effectiveness
of the war system, and the more important reason for hedging with peace
planning, lies in the backwardness of current war-system programming. Its
controls have not kept pace with the technological advances it has made
possible. Despite its inarguable success to date, even in this era of unprecedented
potential in mass destruction, it continues to operate largely on a laissez-faire
basis. To the best of our knowledge, no serious quantified studies have
ever been conducted to determine, for example:
Our final conclusion, therefore, is that it will be necessary for our
government to plan in depth for two general contingencies. The first, and
lesser, is the possibility of a viable general peace; the second is the
successful continuation of the war system. In our view, careful preparation
for the possibility of peace should be extended, not because we take the
position that the end of war would necessarily be desirable, if it is in
fact possible, but because it may be thrust upon us in some form whether
we are ready for it or not. Planning for rationalizing and quantifying
the war system, on the other hand, to ensure the effectiveness of its major
stabilizing functions, is not only more promising in respect to anticipated
results, but is essential; we can no longer take for granted that it will
continue to serve our purposes well merely because it always has. The objective
of government policy in regard to war and peace, in this period of uncertainty,
must be to preserve maximum options. The recommendations which follow are
directed to this end.
(2) The first of the War/Peace Research
Agency's two principal responsibilities will be to determine all that can
be known, including what can reasonably be inferred in terms of relevant
statistical probabilities, that may bear on an eventual transition to a
general condition of peace. The findings in this Report may be considered
to constitute the beginning of this study and to indicate its orientation;
detailed records of the investigations and findings of the Special Study
Group on which this Report is based, will be furnished the agency, along
with whatever clarifying data the agency deems necessary. This aspect of
the agency's work will hereinafter be referred to as "Peace Research."
The Agency's Peace Research activities will necessarily include, but
not be limited to, the following: Peace research methods will include but not be limited to, the following: (3) The War/Peace Research Agency's other principal
responsibility will be "War Research." Its fundamental objective will be
to ensure the continuing viability of the war system to fulfill its essential
nonmilitary functions for as long as the war system is judged necessary
to or desirable for the survival of society. To achieve this end, the War
Research groups within the agency will engage in the following activities:
(a) Quantification of existing application of the nonmilitary
functions of war. Specific determinations will include, but not
be limited to: 1) the gross amount and the net proportion of nonproductive
military expenditures since World War II assignable to the need for war
as an economic stabilizer; 2) the amount and proportion of military expenditures
and destruction of life, property, and natural resources during this period
assignable to the need for war as an instrument for political control;
3) similar figures, to the extent that they can be separately arrived at,
assignable to the need for war to maintain social cohesiveness; 4) levels
of recruitment and expenditures on the draft and other forms of personnel
deployment attributable to the need for military institutions to control
social disaffection; 5) the statistical relationship of war casualties
to world food supplies; 6) the correlation of military actions and expenditures
with cultural activities and scientific advances (including necessarily,
the development of mensurable standards in these areas).
(b) Establishment of a priori modern criteria for the execution
of the nonmilitary functions of war. These will include, but not
be limited to: 1) calculation of minimum and optimum ranges of military
expenditure required, under varying hypothetical conditions, to fulfill
these several functions, separately and collectively; 2) determination
of minimum and optimum levels of destruction of life, property, and natural
resources prerequisite to the credibility of external threat essential
to the political and motivational functions; 3) development of a negotiable
formula governing the relationship between military recruitment and training
policies and the exigencies of social control.
(c) Reconciliation of these criteria with prevailing economic,
political, sociological, and ecological limitations. The ultimate
object of this phase of War Research is to rationalize the heretofore informal
operations of the war system. It should provide practical working procedures
through which responsible governmental authority may resolve the following
war-function problems, among others, under any given circumstances: 1)
how to determine the optimum quantity, nature, and timing of military expenditures
to ensure a desired degree of economic control; 2) how to organize the
recruitment, deployment, and ostensible use of military personnel to ensure
a desired degree of acceptance of authorized social values; 3) how to compute
on a short-term basis, the nature and extent of the loss of life and other
resources which should be suffered and/or inflicted during any single outbreak
of hostilities to achieve a desired degree of internal political authority
and social allegiance; 4) how to project, over extended periods, the nature
and quality of overt warfare which must be planned and budgeted to achieve
a desired degree of contextual stability for the same purpose; factors
to be determined must include frequency of occurrence, length of phase,
intensity of physical destruction, extensiveness of geographical involvement,
and optimum mean loss of life; 5) how to extrapolate accurately from the
foregoing, for ecological purposes, the continuing effect of the war system,
over such extended cycles, on population pressures, and to adjust the planning
of casualty rates accordingly.
War Research procedures will necessarily include, but not be limited
to, the following: (4) Since both programs of the War/Peace Research Agency will share
the same purpose - to maintain governmental freedom of choice in respect
to war and peace until the direction of social survival is no longer in
doubt - it is of the essence of this proposal that the agency be constituted
without limitation of time. Its examination of existing and proposed institutions
will be self-liquidating when its own function shall have been superseded
by the historical developments it will have, at least in part, initiated.
2. Herman Kahn, Thinking About the Unthinkable
(New York: Horizon, 1962), p. 35.
3. Robert S. McNamara, in an address before the American
Society of Newspaper Editors, Montreal, P.Q., Canada, 18 May 1966.
4. Alfred North Whitehead, in "The Anatomy of Some Scientific
Ideas," included in The Aims of Education (New York: Macmillan,
1929).
5. At Ann Arbor, Michigan, 16 June 1962.
6. Louis J. Halle, "Peace in Our Time? Nuclear Weapons
as a Stabilizer," The New Republic (28 December 1963).
7. Kenneth E. Boulding, "The World War Industry as an
Economic Problem," in Emile Benoit and Kenneth E. Boulding (eds.), Disarmament
and the Economy New York: Harper and Row, 1963).
8. McNamara, in ASNE Montreal address cited.
9. Report of the Committee on the Economic Impact
of Defense and Disarmament (Washington: USGPO, July 1965).
10. Sumner M. Rosen, "Disarmament and the Economy,"
War/Peace Report (March 1966).
11. Vide William D. Grampp, "False Fears
of Disarmament," Harvard Business Review (Jan.-Feb. 1964)
for a concise example of this reasoning.
12. Seymour Melman, "The Cost of Inspection for Disarmament,"
in Benoit and Boulding, op. cit.
13. Arthur I. Waskow, Toward the Unarmed Forces
of the United States (Washington: Institute for Policy Studies,
1966), p. 9. (This is the unabridged edition of the text of a report and
proposal prepared for a seminar of strategists and Congressmen in 1965;
it was later given limited distribution among other persons engaged in
related projects.)
14. David T. Bazelon, "The Politics of the Paper Economy,"
Commentary (November 1962), p. 409.
15. The Economic Impact of Disarmament
(Washington: USGPO, January 1962).
16. David T. Bazelon, "The Scarcity Makers," Commentary
(October 1962), p. 298.
17. Frank Pace, Jr., in an address before the American
Bankers' Association, September 1957.
18. A random example, taken in this case from a story
by David Deitch in the New York Herald Tribune (9 February
1966).
19. Vide L. Gumplowicz, in Geschichte
der Staatstheorien (Innsbruck: Wagner, 1905) and earlier writings.
20. K. Fischer, Das Militaer (Zurich:
Steinmetz Verlag, 1932), pp. 42-43.
21. The obverse of this phenomenon is responsible for
the principal combat problem of present-day infantry officers: the unwillingness
of otherwise "trained" troops to fire at an enemy close enough to be recognizable
as an individual rather than simply as a target.
22. Herman Kahn, On Thermonuclear War
(Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1960), p. 42.
23. John D. Williams, "The Nonsense about Safe Driving,"
Fortune (September 1958).
24. Vide most recently K. Lorenz, in
Das Sogenannte Boese: zur Naturgeschichte der Aggression
(Vienna: G. Borotha-Schoeler Verlag, 1964).
25. Beginning with Herbert Spencer and his contemporaries,
but largely ignored for nearly a century.
26. As in recent draft-law controversy, in which the
issue of selective deferment of the culturally privileged is often carelessly
equated with the preservation of the biologically "fittest."
27. G. Bouthoul, in La Guerre (Paris:
Presses universitaires de France, 1953) and many other more detailed studies.
The useful concept of "polemology," for the study of war as an independent
discipline, is his, as is the notion of "demographic relaxation," the sudden
temporary decline in the rate of population increase after major wars.
28. This seemingly premature statement is supported
by one of our own test studies. But it hypothecates both the stabilizing
of world population growth and the institution of fully adequate environmental
controls. Under these two conditions, the probability of the permanent
elimination of involuntary global famine is 68 percent by 1976 and 95 percent
by 1981.
29. This round figure is the median taken from our
computations, which cover varying contingencies, but it is sufficient for
the purpose of general discussion.
30. But less misleading than the more elegant traditional
metaphor, in which war expenditures are referred to as the "ballast" of
the economy but which suggests incorrect quantitative relationships.
31. Typical in generality, scope, and rhetoric. We
have not used any published program as a model; similarities are unavoidably
coincidental rather than tendentious.
32. Vide the reception of a "Freedom
Budget for all Americans," proposed by A. Philip Randolph et al;
it is a ten-year plan, estimated by its sponsors to cost $185 billion.
34. By several current theorists, most extensively
and effectively by Robert R. Harris in The Real Enemy, an
unpublished doctoral dissertation made available to this study.
35. In ASNE Montreal address cited.
37. For an examination of some of its social implications,
see Seymour Rubenfeld, Family of Outcasts: A New Theory of Delinquency
(New York: Free Press, 1965).
38. As in Nazi Germany; this type of "ideological"
ethnic repression, directed to specific sociological ends, should not be
confused with traditional economic exploitation, as of Negroes in the U.S.,
South Africa, etc.
39. By teams of experimental biologists in Massachusetts,
Michigan, and California, as well as in Mexico and the U.S.S.R. Preliminary
test applications are scheduled in Southeast Asia, in countries not yet
announced.
40. Expressed in the writings of H. Marshall McLuhan,
in Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man (New York:
McGraw-Hill, 1964) and elsewhere.
41. This rather optimistic estimate was derived by
plotting a three-dimensional distribution of three arbitrarily defined
variables; the macro-structural, relating to the extension of knowledge
beyond the capacity of conscious experience; the organic, dealing with
the manifestations of terrestrial life as inherently comprehensible; and
the infra-particular, covering the subconceptual requirements of natural
phenomena. Values were assigned to the known and unknown in each parameter,
tested against data from earlier chronologies, and modified heuristically
until predictable correlations reached a useful level of accuracy. "Two
decades" means, in this case, 20.6 years, with a standard deviation of
only 1.8 years. (An incidental finding, not pursued to the same degree
of accuracy, suggests a greatly accelerated resolution of issues in the
biological sciences after 1972.)
42. Since they represent an examination of too small
a percentage of the eventual options, in terms of "multiple mating," the
subsystem we developed for this application. But an example will indicate
how one of the most frequently recurring correlation problems - chronological
phasing - was brought to light in this way. One of the first combinations
tested showed remarkably high coefficients of compatibility, on a post
hoc static basis, but no variations of timing, using a thirty-year
transition module, permitted even marginal synchronization. The combination
was thus disqualified. This would not rule out the possible adequacy of
combinations using modifications of the same factors, however, since minor
variations in a proposed final condition may have disproportionate effects
on phasing.
43. Edward Teller, quoted in War/Peace Report
(December 1964).
44. E.g., the highly publicized "Delphi technique"
and other, more sophisticated procedures. A new system, especially suitable
for institutional analysis, was developed during the course of this study
in order to hypothecate mensurable "peace games"; a manual of this system
is being prepared and will be submitted for general distribution among
appropriate agencies. For older, but still useful, techniques, see Norman
C. Dalkey's Games and Simulations (Santa Monica, Calif.:
Rand, 1964).
45. A primer-level example of the obvious and long
overdue need for such translation is furnished by Kahn (in Thinking
About the Unthinkable, p. 102). Under the heading "Some Awkward
Choices" he compares four hypothetical policies: a certain loss of $3,000;
a .1 chance of loss of $300,000; a .01 chance of loss of $30,000,000; and
a .001 chance of loss of $3,000,000,000. A government decision-maker would
"very likely" choose in that order. But what if "lives are at stake rather
than dollars"? Kahn suggests that the order of choice would be reversed,
although current experience does not support this opinion. Rational war
research can and must make it possible to express, without ambiguity, lives
in terms of dollars and vice versa; the choices need not be, and cannot
be, "awkward."
46. Again, an overdue extension of an obvious application
of techniques up to now limited to such circumscribed purposes as improving
kill-ammunition ratios determining local choice between precision and saturation
bombing, and other minor tactical, and occasionally strategic, ends. The
slowness of Rand, I.D.A., and other responsible analytic organizations
to extend cost-effectiveness and related concepts beyond early-phase applications
has already been widely remarked on and criticized elsewhere.
47. The inclusion of institutional factors in war-game
techniques has been given some rudimentary consideration in the Hudson
Institute's Study for Hypothetical Narratives for Use in Command
and Control Systems Planning (by William Pfaff and Edmund Stillman;
Final report published 1963). But here, as with other war and peace studies
to date, what has blocked the logical extension of new analytic techniques
has been a general failure to understand and properly evaluate the nonmilitary
functions of war.
New York Times Book Review: March 19, 1972Other
SECTION 6: Substitutes for the Functions of War
Economic
Political
Sociological
Of the many functions of war we have found convenient to group together
in this classification, two are critical. In a world of peace, the continuing
stability of society will require: 1) an effective substitute for military
institutions that can neutralize destabilizing social elements and 2) a
credible motivational surrogate for war that can insure social cohesiveness.
The first is an essential element of social control; the second is the
basic mechanism for adapting individual human drives to the needs of society.
"It seems to me that we could move toward remedying that inequity
[of the Selective Service System] by asking every young person in the United
States to give two years of service to his country - whether in one of
the military services, in the Peace Corps, or in some other volunteer developmental
work at home or abroad. We could encourage other countries to do the same."
[35]
Here, as elsewhere throughout this significant speech, Mr. McNamara has
focused, indirectly but unmistakably, on one of the key issues bearing
on a possible transition to peace, and has later indicated, also indirectly,
a rough approach to its resolution, again phrased in the language of the
current war system.
Ecological
Cultural and Scientific
SECTION 7: Summary and Conclusions
Sociological: Control function. Although the various substitutes
proposed for this function that are modeled roughly on the Peace Corps
appear grossly inadequate in potential scope, they should not be ruled
out without further study. Slavery, in a technologically modern and conceptually
euphemized form, may prove a more efficient and flexible institution in
this area. Motivational function. Although none of the proposed
substitutes for war as the guarantor of social allegiance can be dismissed
out of hand, each presents serious and special difficulties. Intensified
environmental threats may raise ecological dangers; mythmaking dissociated
from war may no longer be politically feasible; purposeful blood games
and rituals can far more readily be devised than implemented. An institution
combining this function with the preceding one, based on, but not necessarily
imitative of, the precedent of organized ethnic repression, warrants careful
consideration.
General Conclusions
These and other war-function factors are fully susceptible to analysis
by today's computer-based systems, [44] but they have
not been so treated; modern analytical techniques have up to now been relegated
to such aspects of the ostensible functions of war as procurement, personnel
deployment, weapons analysis, and the like. We do not disparage these types
of application, but only deplore their lack of utilization to greater capacity
in attacking problems of broader scope. Our concern for efficiency in this
context is not aesthetic, economic, or humanistic. It stems from the axiom
that no system can long survive at either input or output levels that consistently
or substantially deviate from an optimum range. As their data grow increasingly
sophisticated, the war system and its functions are increasingly endangered
by such deviations.
SECTION 8: Recommendations
(a)
The creative development of possible substitute institutions for the
principal nonmilitary functions of war. (b)
The careful matching of such institutions against the criteria summarized
in this Report, as refined, revised, and extended by the agency. (c)
The testing and evaluation of substitute institutions, for acceptability,
feasibility, and credibility, against hypothecated transitional and postwar
conditions; the testing and evaluation of the effects of the anticipated
atrophy of certain unsubstituted functions. (d)
The development and testing of the correlativity of multiple substitute
institutions, with the eventual objective of establishing a comprehensive
program of compatible war substitutes suitable for a planned transition
to peace, if and when this is found to be possible and subsequently judged
desirable by appropriate political authorities. (e)
The preparation of a wide-ranging schedule of partial, uncorrelated,
crash programs of adjustment suitable for reducing the dangers of an unplanned
transition to peace effected by force majeure. (a)
The comprehensive interdisciplinary application of historical, scientific,
technological, and cultural data. (b)
The full utilization of modern methods of mathematical modeling, analogical
analysis, and other, more sophisticated, quantitative techniques in process
of development that are compatible with computer programming. (c)
The heuristic "peace games" procedures developed during the course
of its assignment by the Special Study Group, and further extensions of
this basic approach to the testing of institutional functions. (a)
The collation of economic, military, and other relevant data into
uniform terms, permitting the reversible translation of heretofore discrete
categories of information. [45] (b)
The development and application of appropriate forms of cost-effectiveness
analysis suitable for adapting such new constructs to computer terminology,
programming, and projection. [46] (c)
Extension of the "war games" methods of systems testing to apply,
as a quasi-adversary proceeding, to the nonmilitary functions of war. [47]
Notes
"Report From Iron Mountain"
'The Guest Word' - By LEONARD LEWIN